Just five minutes…
Dr. Dimitrios Karathanassis
In: ContraLegem 2021/2, S. 4ff.
- The change of law through the acceleration of the economy and social structures.
- The law is increasingly exposed to social changes occurring at shorter intervals. This endangers fundamental principles of constitutional law.
When Marcel Niggli, editor-in-chief and publisher of ContraLegem, asked me if I would like to join the editorial staff of ContraLegem, it took me less than five minutes to accept. This may sound like a quick shot, a lack of consideration, but five minutes is a small eternity in today’s media society. Some may smile, perhaps disagree, even demand a somewhat in-depth clarification from a lawyer, but for a tweet that sends hundreds onto the streets and encourages them to attack people, storm state and private buildings and block roads, it really doesn’t take much longer. So five minutes for a decision is relative. One may rightly object that personal decisions have always been made in significantly shorter periods of time, one thinks of the famous “gut decisions”. But what is acceptable for personal decisions now also seems to apply to social communication through the immediacy of the means of communication (keyword: social media). The tweets already mentioned illustrate this perfectly.
It is therefore not surprising that politicians are desperately trying to keep up with the speed of communication in the media society and that political debates are increasingly tempo and less This is the first time that we have had a debate on this subject in the European Now, social acceleration in communication is not a phenomenon of our time, telegrams, telephones and faxes have always exerted accelerating effects on the respective social structures. And politics has always been guided by this stream of accelerating communication, for example election campaigns at the beginning of the 19th century. It is located in the district of São Paulo.
What is new, however, is that the judiciary allows itself to be harnessed into this game of race. Of course, if politics and its means of communication change, the judiciary will (have to) adapt to it, but for some time now , It is a question of adopting the functioning of the policy tel quel. Focusing on speed rather than content may be useful, perhaps even necessary, for policy, but it means that the end rather than the means are increasingly coming to the fore. when it comes to formulating and debating political goals. For an increasing concentration on tempo allows only the intended end to be formulated, while the explanation of the means and the critical consideration of the end raise questions of In this context , it is important to stress the importance of the role of the social partners in the competition because there is simply no time for this and because the audience’s attention span is less and less sufficient for this. The climate debate makes this very clear: the climate must be saved and everything must be subordinated to this goal. The discussion as to whether the proposed means (reduction of CO2 emissions, subsidization of electric cars, etc.) suitable 5and appropriate, has little chance to develop.
For the judiciary and the law in general, this means that they increasingly focus on the purpose and clear legal institutions and guidelines that slow down the – rapid – achievement of the purpose. could be dubbed. The ruling of the Lausanne District Court – to stay with the climate debate – which had protected the occupation of a bank branch by activists as a justifying emergency, instead of dismissing it because of Condemning trespassing is only one prominent example (cf. see our videos 1a and 1b). The reference to the justifying state of emergency, which one cannot get rid of in any case, was less the result of a clean legal dispute, but arose from the The need arises as a court to somehow justify the exculpation of young people, which is perceived as politically and medially correct (we are not yet to the extent that judgments are given without justification).
It is undisputed that justice and justice are never completely detached from politics. Don’t forget that the country’s top judges are nominated by political parties (and are coming under increasing political pressure). However, it is problematic when the judiciary and the law adapt to politics so much (one is inclined to say: currying favor) that the boundaries of political debate and legal structures are becoming blurred. Of course, this is not a plea for justice and a law that should not change . However , they are intended to provide politics and society with the structures that we know after so many bad experiences in Europe’s past that minorities are minorities. protect, guarantee the rule of law and strive for a balance in the weighting of arguments. If one aims only at the purpose, the door opens for a dynamic that makes maximum demands and has no time for compromises. This is because compromises are possible in terms of means rather than ends. It remains irrelevant whether the lack of time is the symptom of a fast-paced world or is used as a means of avoiding discussion. If maximum demands are then accompanied by a moral claim to be on the right side of history, then – despite or precisely because of the Claim to do good for all people – a totalitarian path taken. Hell is known to be full of people who wanted good.
This has become clear in almost every major political debate in recent months, be it in relation to climate rescue, women’s rights, gender debate or BlackLivesMatter: The political actors and the media do not formulate negotiable maximum demands, stifle criticism in the approach and thus prevent any critical debate. But those who make maximum demands and place only the purpose at the centre of political life are putting the cart before the horse . For while a free society should debate the guidelines within which everyone should be able to develop and seize their opportunities, recent political discussions appear Always results-oriented. If one breaks the whole thing down to the original element of every political discussion, that of justice and its core, equality, then a change of equal opportunities emerges. away and towards equality of results.
However, a society that strives for equality of results is by definition totalitarian, because equality does not allow other interests to develop as a result. All other results are understood as annoying at best, as an attack at worst. And a society that of its own accord defines or allows to be defined equality of results (what it must do in order to achieve it) must also necessarily claim to 6the absolute truth and to know the good in itself. Because only if the truth and the good are known, the desired result can be legitimized. A result that can be achieved by all, which is not based on truth and goodness, is inevitably delegitimized by arbitrariness, so that it begins to falter. The fact that the definition of truth and good is also exposed to arbitrariness is , of course, another piece of paper.
This development is reinforced by the fact that equality of results has it easier in a world that measures and quantifies everything. The development of recent years shows that decisions – including political ones – are increasingly based on these measurements and quantifications, namely through collected data sets, be taken. Concrete results can be measured, quantified and bundled as data sets, while the question of opportunities always requires lengthy analysis. It should therefore come as no surprise that the increasing depiction of human action in data sets politically and in the media favours equality of results. As a result, measuring and presenting pointedly is easier to understand than lengthy debates about whether there are equal opportunities for everyone.
Finally, the fixation on equality of results also avoids the difficult confrontation with (personal) responsibility. If the purpose is clearly formulated and the desired result is defined, then personal failure as well as personal success become secondary, because the lead lies with the Collective. Questions about the individual use of (equal) opportunities and the resulting consequences become superfluous, because only the result counts. However, this also means that where the individual deviates and does not or does not want to achieve the result on his own , the collective claims to intervene. The debate on the question of whether school canteens are allowed to offer meat shows that such intervention can be achieved first through incentives (keyword “nudging”) and then through bans. is carried out.
If one steps into observant distance, it becomes clear that this political and increasingly legal development ultimately amounts to a concrete result: the reversal of a long-standing , in the West hard-won order on the ideals of the Enlightenment. The question of the “who”, the “actor” and his characteristics is increasingly becoming the focus of discussions. For this, the discussion after the action, the discussion about the evaluation of a certain action (or omission) is suppressed. This is hardly surprising, because the fixation on results favors the “who” over the action, because characteristics (age, gender, skin color , etc.) are more objectifiable – and therefore more measurable – than actions in which the subjective element always causes difficulties. But those who (again) begin to evaluate people – especially legally – according to their characteristics, cannot avoid categories (of people) to create. The ever-increasing number of genders makes this clear and paradoxically emphasizes (in an inevitably discriminatory way) the question of gender rather than gender to overcome them. But then political and media categories of people (LGBT members, white old men, women, blacks, etc.) The road to Auschwitz has finally begun. And here, too, good intentions do not give any security not to end up there, but rather increase the danger. Anyone who divides people into categories – even if only for a noble goal – inevitably discriminates. And so we run the risk that law no longer primarily evaluates actions (or omissions), but the qualities of man. When the Cyclops, blinded by Odysseus, asks him screaming for his name, he answers only with “Outis”. Nobody. And this nobody is the foundation of our liberal 7Western civilization. The monster is not confronted with the qualities of man, but it is forced to be content with the action of the individual and to deal with it. . No one is everyone, and therefore irrelevant. The plot is relevant and it is not for nothing that Odysseus’ torments begin when he reveals himself in a fit of megalomania.
A judgment delivered this year by the European Court of Human Rights (Vavricka and others v. The Czech Republic), which supports the obligation for children in the Czech Republic (regardless of the COVID pandemic), clearly shows that in order to answer the question of whether the public interest (compulsory vaccination for the purpose of Prevention of the spread of a disease) or the individual interest (right to refuse vaccination) is preferred, two categories were decisive: vaccinated vs. Unvaccinated. One judge rightly pointed out in his dissenting opinion that a serious debate on whether the refusal of vaccination for non-communicable diseases would be in the The same mass had to be subordinated to the common good (i.e. the obligation to vaccinate) as in the case of infectious diseases. As a result, the court decided on the basis of the categories vaccinated/unvaccinated, based on the desired result, not on the basis of the chosen means. Think of the five minutes mentioned at the beginning: they are never enough to evaluate an action, however clear, the subjective and objective To identify the facts of this act, to examine the causality of damages or profits. However, five minutes are sufficient with the help of technical means to capture primary and secondary characteristics of a person. The central question remains: do we want legal consequences based on the five minutes? What may be sufficient for a personal decision and based on intuition must not become the yardstick of a legal system.
The creation of categories also has the consequence that those assigned to them are understood as a collective. For example, the debate on women’s equality assumes that all women have the same concerns and needs. These and similar debates are conducted so sharply that it is hardly possible to seriously discuss why there are far fewer women than men in companies. Management positions . It is simply demanded that this must change in the future. Apart from the fact that all people of the female sex are treated as a collective with identical wishes and needs, it shows a worldview that the clothing a management position in a company as the ultimate goal of professional realization. As a result, quotas are not only imposed on companies, but also a uniform and by no means undisputed world view is given to women as an ideal. The debate on women’s equality is a good example because it is, at its core, a political debate that does not promote legal equality. , i.e. equality (which already exists), but the social equality of women. The fact that legal means are required for this ( cf. Art. 734f CO) does not change this, but merely clearly shows that the law (equal rights for all, which is already is politically instrumentalised in order to achieve equality of results at the level of company (law) (as many men as women in certain countries). Management positions). It is not for nothing that these quotas are most strongly rejected by women who already hold management positions. The performance principle as an inherent part of any debate about equal opportunities gives way here to a vehemently demanded but reduced to the gender of the cadre equality of results. If one also wanted to be consistent, one would have to ask oneself why a 50 /50 quota in management positions should not also apply in other professions – and why it should be 8 It is only possible for management positions at all, and not for all levels.
Finally, the renunciation of the ideals of the Enlightenment also means that morality now takes precedence over law. For enlightenment may no longer be en vogue in a collectivist world, but at least it provides the ethical and ideological foundation that makes a liberal constitutional state possible in the first place. If one rejects the ideals of the Enlightenment, one would at least have to have the courage to reject the liberal constitutional state and to demand a system of values oriented towards characteristics rather than actions. . There are plenty of states that serve as role models, past and present. Whether the groups that feel discriminated against would be better off in these models/states may of course be doubted. What is uneasy, however, is the fact that the collectivist currents in the West go hand in hand with the strengthening of collectivist orders in China, Russia and the immediate Periphery of Europe and it is only irony of history that the collectivist-oriented morality that permeates our political debates is the Kerkoporta, by totalitarian ideas penetrate the liberal value system of the West.